<br />Joseph H. Connell
<br />
<br />probably the first demonstration of this:
<br />"If turf which has long been mown, and
<br />the case would be the same with turf
<br />closely browsed by quadrupeds, be let to
<br />grow, the more vigorous plants gradually
<br />kill the less vigorous, though fully grown
<br />plants; thus out of twenty species growing
<br />on a little plot of mown turf (three feet
<br />by four) nine species perished, from the
<br />other species being allowed to grow up
<br />freely." Hutchinson (1961), Paine (1966),
<br />and Connell (1971) have suggested the
<br />same thing, and MacArthur (1972) states:
<br />"If abundant predators prevent any spe-
<br />cies from becoming common, the entire
<br />picture changes. Resources are no longer
<br />of any concern and our Eqs. (I) and (2)
<br />are irrelevant. More correctly, resources
<br />are still a concern, but their manner of
<br />subdivision is irrelevant." The question I
<br />would like to try to answer is, when does
<br />predation, or any factor other than com-
<br />petition, limit the distribution or abun-
<br />dance of a species and so affect its role
<br />in cOmmunity structure? Under which
<br />conditions does competition determine the
<br />shape and size of the realized niche and
<br />which not?
<br />
<br />A Note on Methods
<br />I will first consider the problem of how
<br />to detect and measure the extent of bio-
<br />logical interactions such as competition or
<br />predation. In my opinion this has been the
<br />main stumbling block in testing the valid-
<br />ity of models of community structure.
<br />There seem to have been at least three
<br />general methods used to detect or measure
<br />biological interactions under natural con-
<br />
<br />462
<br />
<br />ditions. The first is to describe the pattern
<br />that exists at a point in time to see
<br />whether it does or does not conform to the
<br />predictions of the model. Some examples
<br />of this are gradient analysis (Whittaker,
<br />1967, 1970; Terborgh, 1971), fitting re]a-
<br />tive abundances to various mathematical
<br />models (MacArthur, 1960; Whittaker,
<br />]965; Levins, 1968), and examining the
<br />distribution patterns, food habits, etc., of
<br />closely related species to see how much
<br />their niches overlap. This method is very
<br />useful in detecting patterns and suggesting
<br />hypotheses for testing.
<br />The second approach is an attempt to
<br />apply the experimental method but with-
<br />out using controls. It consists of searching
<br />for a "natural experiment." For example,
<br />if two similar species occupy the upper
<br />and lower halves of a mountain, rt"spec-
<br />tively, with little or no overlap, one hy-
<br />pothesis is that they exclude each pther
<br />by competition for resources. To test this
<br />hypothesis, one looks for a nearby moun-
<br />tain where one or the other is missing
<br />(e.g., Diamond, Chapter 14, Figure 39). If
<br />competition determines the boundary, the
<br />species present should extend beyond the
<br />boundary on this second mountain. The
<br />trouble with such "natural experiments"
<br />is that an essential part of all true experi-
<br />ments is missing: a control. There is no
<br />certainty that the only difference between
<br />the two mountains is the absence ,)f one
<br />of the species. A predator may have been
<br />absent, or an essential food organ;sm, soil
<br />nutrient, etc., may have been present be-
<br />yond the boundary on the second moun-
<br />tain.
<br />
<br />
<br />16 Producing Structure in Natural
<br />Communities
<br />
<br />The third and, in my opinion the best,
<br />method for revealing the extent of biolog-
<br />ical interactions is the controlled field ex-
<br />periment, whose essential aspect is that
<br />everything varies in the same way be-
<br />tween treatment and control except for the
<br />factor being tested (see review by Connell,
<br />1974). In the example above, instead of
<br />looking for a mountain with one species
<br />missing, one finds another with both spe-
<br />cies in the same arrangement and then
<br />removes one species. The most efficient
<br />thing would, be to remove it near the
<br />boundary; if the other species extends its
<br />range into the vacant territory, competi-
<br />tion is the most likely mechanism pro-
<br />ducing the original boundary. If not, the
<br />hypothesis can be rejected forthwith.
<br />Such field experiments need careful
<br />desion. The trick is to make sure that all
<br />envi~onmental factors, except the one
<br />being tested, vary in the same way and
<br />to the same degree on both experimental
<br />and control sites. Since there are bound
<br />to be some differences, replication is es-
<br />sential. Often it is more difficult to arrange
<br />adequate control sites than to perform the
<br />treatments.
<br />The effect of the experimental treat-
<br />ment itself must be taken into account.
<br />The simplest treatment, removal of one or
<br />more species, is probably the best. Alter-
<br />natively, animals are sometimes intro-
<br />duced into pens or cages (Jaeger, 197 I;
<br />Wilbur, 1972; Grant, 1972). This may
<br />cause problems. First, if emigration is the
<br />usual result of aggressive encounters, this
<br />will be prevented and unusual outcomes
<br />may ensue (Krebs, Keller, and Tamarin,
<br />
<br />463
<br />
<br />1969). Secondly, other species of competi-
<br />tors or predators, which would normally
<br />have influenced the outcome, may be ex-
<br />cluded. If enclosures must be used, these
<br />and other such effects need to be taken
<br />into account in the final interpretation of
<br />the experimental results.
<br />The superiority of such controlled ex-
<br />periments to "natural" ones seems obvi-
<br />ous, yet field experiments are rare in all
<br />ecological literature. One reason is that it
<br />is very difficult to change the abundance
<br />of large or highly mobile animals such as
<br />birds or large mammals. Also, tradition
<br />dictates that experiments are done in lab-
<br />oratories, whereas ecology is done out-
<br />doors. Field trials are relegated to agricul-
<br />ture or forestry, and ecology students
<br />seldom take courses in these areas. But
<br />applied scientists need answers, and ne-
<br />cessity stimulated the development both
<br />of statistical techniques and of field ex-
<br />periments. Most ecologists have adopted
<br />the former but not the latter, to their cost.
<br />In the following section I present a re-
<br />view of the evidence of where competition
<br />occurs in natural communities and where
<br />it is prevented by predation or physical
<br />conditions. The aim of this review is to see
<br />whether there is any pattern in the occur-
<br />rence of competition. I have used evidence
<br />from controlled field experiments when-
<br />ever possible, both to illustrate their value
<br />and to suggest where they could be used
<br />in the future. Although the number of
<br />instances where field experiments have
<br />been used are few, they differentiate be-
<br />tween the alternatives clearly in a way
<br />that correlations between abundances,
<br />
<br />
<br />
|